Return to Home Page

 

Marxism and Method

Daniel Little

University of Michigan-Dearborn

Introduction

      This essay is concerned with Marxist method in the twentieth century.  Before proceeding far, however, we have to ask the question—what sort of method are we considering?  It is a fact that Marxist thought has inspired research frameworks in many fields—art history, literature, culture studies, philosophy, historiography, and the social sciences.  And these influences have proceeded through many different tropes within Marx’s thought—the theory of alienation, the concept of mystification, the labor theory of value, the theories of class conflict and exploitation, the theory of the forces and relations of production, or the theory of the mode of production.  So the question of Marxist method is complicated in a many-many way: there are many areas where Marxist methods have been employed, and there are many strands within Marx’s thought that have given rise to these various approaches.

      My focus will be on methodology for the social sciences (within which I include much of historical inquiry).  This choice sets two basic parameters to our study.  We will be concerned with the ways in which Marxist methods have in the past century helped to shape our understanding of the social world.  And we will be concerned with these influences within the domain of empirical research (as opposed to literary, philosophical, or ethical investigations). 

      Marx is one of the unmistakable founders of modern social science.  Throughout a lifetime of research and writing he aimed to arrive at a scientific analysis of modern economic life.  Throughout most of his life he emphasized the importance of engaging in a scientific analysis of capitalism as a system.  And he consistently adhered to a rigorous commitment to honest empirical investigation of the facts.  Marx’s own goals were thus undoubtedly framed by his aspiration to construct a scientific analysis of the capitalist mode of production.  And social science research and theory today is certainly strongly influenced by many of Marx’s contributions—especially in the areas of social history, sociology, and political economy.  Here I will survey some of the important avenues through which Marxist approaches to the social sciences have developed in the twentieth century.  And I will attempt to provide perspective on the enduring contributions that Marxist social science has made for the conduct of social research.

      The influence of Marx’s thought in the social sciences in the twentieth century is ubiquitous: social history and the history of working people (Jones 1971); institutions within capitalism (Giddens 1973); political history of revolution and class (Soboul 1989); the lived experience of the working class (Sennett and Cobb 1972); alienation and mystification as social categories and real social phenomena (manufacturing and its culture) (Szymanski 1978), (Mészáros 1972); political economy (Mandel 1969, 1975), sociology of education (Bowles and Gintis 1976); the state within capitalist societies (Miliband 1969, 1982), (Poulantzas 1973).  Marx’s writings have contributed enormously to how we analyze, conceptualize, and explain social processes and social history.

      However, there is no single answer to the question, “What is the Marxist methodology of social science?”  Rather, Marxist social inquiry in the twentieth century represents a chorus of many voices and insights, many of which are inconsistent with others.  Rather than representing a coherent research community in possession of a central paradigm and commitment to specific methodological and theoretical premises, Marxist social science in the twentieth century has had a great deal of variety and diversity of emphases.  Think of the range of thinkers whose work falls within the general category of Marxian social science: E. P. Thompson, Louis Althusser, Jürgen Habermas, Gerald Cohen, Robert Brenner, Nicos Poulantzas, Ralph Miliband, Nikolai Bukharin, Georg Lukàcs, or Michel Foucault.  All these authors have made a contribution to Marxist social science; but in no way do these contributions add up to a single, coherent and focused methodology for the social sciences.  There is no canonical body of findings that constitute a paradigm.  Instead, there are numerous signal instances of substantive and methodological writings, from a variety of traditions, that have provided moments of insight and locations for possible future research. And so the graduate student of the social sciences who aims to acquire expertise in “Marxist theory” will find her course of study to more closely resemble that of a literature student than a student of molecular biology with an open-ended set of encounters with great works than a coherent and orderly research discipline.

 “Methodology for social science research”?

      Why do we need a methodology for the social sciences?  Because the social world is indefinitely complex and multi-stranded—thus eluding explanation through simple observation.  And because the social world as a domain of phenomena is fundamentally different from the natural world, in the respect of its degree of “law-governedness” (Little 1993).  So neither the methods of ordinary commonsense nor the methods of the natural sciences will suffice to lead us to an ability to recognize the systems, structures, and causal processes that are embodied in the social world.  The social world proceeds through the activities of billions of men and women.  It embodies institutions, organizations, and structures that propel and constrain individual action, and these social entities give rist to processes that are neither law-governed nor random.  The social world gives rise to relations of power, domination, exploitation, and resistance.  It produces outcomes that advantage some and disadvantage others.  It is the result of complex exchanges between agents and structures, and each pole of this conjunction influences the other.  The social world, in short, is complex.  The challenge of understanding social phenomena is both important and difficult.  This is true in 2000; but it was not less true in 1830, when Engels took up residence in Birmingham and undertook to describe and comprehend the confusion of factories, slums, mansions, hunger, and turmoil that Birmingham represented.  The Conditions of the Working Class in England is his result (Engels 1958); and Capital is Marx’s (Marx 1977).

      What is involved in having a “philosophy and methodology for social science”?  It is to have answers to several different domains of questions—

 

·      inquiry—how to make use of a variety of tools of research to arrive at hypotheses and theories about a domain of empirical phenomena;

·      epistemology—how to employ empirical and theoretical considerations to provide justification for the hypotheses and theories that we put forward;

·      metaphysics—an account of the types of entities and processes of which the domain of phenomena are composed; and

·      a theory of the structure of social science knowledge—a conception of the purpose of social science inquiry and a schematic notion of what social science results ought to look like.  (Theories?  Bodies of empirical findings?  Statistical laws?  Narrative interpretations of important social processes?  Groups of causal hypotheses?)

 

      Marx’s methodological thinking, and that of many Marxist social scientists who followed, provide tentative answers to each of these questions.  And, as we should expect, these answers add up to something less than a finished and consistent methodology (any more than Weber’s work constitutes a tidy theory of social science knowledge and inquiry; (Ringer 1997)).

The social science aim of Marxism

      Let us begin with Marx’s social science contributions themselves.  It is fruitful to ask the question, what are Marx’s central aims as a social scientist?  And in what does his central contribution consist?  Does his work, and the work that followed from it, provide a theory of capitalism and history?  Are there specific empirical hypotheses that are subject to empirical investigation in his work?  Does it provide a paradigm or research programme, along the lines articulated by Kuhn and Lakatos (Lakatos 1970; Lakatos and Musgrave 1974; Kuhn 1970)?  Does Marx adhere to a coherent conception of social inquiry and social explanation?  And does Marx have a distinctive conception of social science inquiry—a theory of dialectical reasoning, for example?[1]

      Marx’s central scientific goals include at least these: to provide an empirically well-founded description of the central institutional features of a market-based property holding economic system; to derive the social implications of these institutional arrangements; and to illuminate the historical process through which these institutional features came to exist in the several capitalist social economies.  His central social scientific contribution is Capital (Marx 1977), and this work is a dense mélange of historical description, micro-sociological detail, reasoning about institutions and their implications, and mathematical political economy.  (These points are more fully developed in (Little 1986).)  Marx believed that the institutions of capitalism constituted a mode of production, and that this mode of production has a distinctive historical logic.  Ordinary men and women, pursuing their lives within the institutional context of capitalism, make choices in private life, work life, and a variety of organizations (firms, unions, parties), that lead collectively to large-scale patterns of change.  Processes of accumulation of capital, acceleration of technological change, and clarification of classes (proletariat, bourgeoisie) are the predictable consequence of the defining institutional setting of capitalist development.  Socially constructed individuals within specific institutions behave in predictable ways—leading to a process of social change that can be delineated and explained. There is hence an institutional logic defined by private ownership in the means of production and wage labor, and working out some of the consequences of this logic is one of Marx’s central goals.  So Marx’s social science writings are best understood as constituting a diverse set of lines of thought, explanatory models, and historical interpretations falling loosely under a guiding perspective on historical and social change.

      On this interpretation, Marx’s contribution to the social sciences is something other than a coherent and simple theory of capitalism.  He provides knowledge about capitalism as a social order; but this knowledge cannot be summarized in a formal or mathematical theory with a small number of premises.  Rather, it is comprised of an irreducible variety of sociological description, historical interpretation (now often superceded by better knowledge about the feudal world or early capitalism), and quasi-formal reasoning about institutions and economic relations. 

      Is there at least a coherent theory of social science inquiry in Marx’s writings?  Marx certainly provides guidance for other historical and social researchers, in terms of where to look for hypotheses.  So there is a Marxist “style of inquiry” that has specific origins in Marx’s own research.  This style of inquiry has a number of features.  It is materialist—that is, it focuses on the forces and relations of production, and it postulates that technology and power are fundamental with regard to other social formations (e.g. literature, culture, law).  It is oriented to the salience of class and class conflict within historical change.  It is sensitive to the workings of ideology and false consciousness in our understandings of the social institutions within which we live.  And it pays special interest, and offers special concern, to the perspectives of the underclasses at any given time in history. 

      What about dialectics, and Marx’s famous assertion that he has turned Hegel’s dialectical logic on its head?  Contrary to a number of interpreters of Marx (Ollman 1971), (Ruben 1979; Ollman 1993; Schaff 1970), I maintain that the concept of dialectics plays only a minor role in Marx’s thinking, and no role at all in his method of inquiry (Little 1987).  The role that dialectics plays is more by way of a high-level hypothesis about institutional change—that institutions have unforeseen and unintended consequences; that processes of change can bring about an undermining of the foundations of the institutions driving these processes of change; and that there are “contradictions” in historical processes.  But this is no more mysterious than Mancur Olsen’s discovery of the contradiction between private and collective interests (Olson 1965), Kenneth Arrow’s demonstration of the impossibility of a consistent voting scheme (Arrow 1963), or George Akerlof’s analysis of the perverse consequences of information asymmetry in competitive markets (Akerlof 1970).  Social science research has almost always made its more important contributions through discovery of unintended consequences and perverse effects; and this is very much the role that dialectics plays in Marx’s writings.

      Much of the most constructive work in Marxian social science in the past 20 years has taken place within the framework of “rational choice Marxism”—authors such as Elster (Elster 1982, 1985, 1986), Roemer (Roemer 1981, 1982, 1982, 1986, 1986), Brenner (Brenner 1976, 1982), and Przeworski (Przeworski 1985, 1985, 1986) who have attempted to bring together Marxian historical insights with the methodology of rational choice theory and the new institutionalism (Powell and DiMaggio 1996; Brinton and Nee 1998), (Knight 1992).  On this approach, it is argued that we can reach Marxian conclusions (about exploitation, class, and the tendencies of capitalism, for example) on the basis of the assumption of individual rationality within the specific institutional setting of capitalism.  What this demonstrates is that the essential Marxian contribution is substantive, not methodological; it is a set of discoveries about the social world, not an artifact of a particular conception of inquiry. 

      Is the rational choice approach compatible with Marx’s own methodology?  I believe that it is.  First, Marx’s use of the tools of political economy, and his central demonstrations of the laws of capitalism, depend on the assumption of individual rationality.  Second, Marx’s approach to method is, as argued above, eclectic.  So we would not expect him to reject an approach that promises to provide rigorous empirical and theoretical support for his analysis.  And in fact, it is possible to discern the workings of rational choice analysis at the core of Marx’s most favored discoveries.  Marx’s argument for the falling rate of profit, for example, hinges on a very Olson-like argument (Olson 1965) concerning the contradiction between the individual capitalist’s interests and the interests of the class of capitalists as a whole.  And this is an argument within the theory of rational choice. 

      Marx’s method of inquiry, then, is unexceptional; it is not sharply distinguished from non-Marxist social science.  Marx emphasizes the importance of careful empirical and historical inquiry.  He values explanatory hypotheses that can be rigorously developed in such a way as to explain and predict social outcomes.  He is not antecedently wedded to particular interpretations of history (for example, recall his agnostic statements about Russian economic development to Vera Zasulich; (Marx and Engels 1975 : 319-320)).  And he constructs his own inquiry around a set of high-level research hypotheses—the salience of class, the importance of the material foundations of social institutions, and the workings of ideology.  Finally, Marx offers what might be called a “galilean” model of social explanation: to explain phenomena in terms of underlying causal conditions rather than crude associations among observable variables.  This perspective leads him to engage in careful hypothesis-formation—again, a perspective that is highly consistent with contemporary social science research standards.

      Does Marx have a distinctive epistemology for the social sciences?  As suggested in this treatment of theory and inquiry, I take the position that he does not.  His epistemology is comparable to what we might today call a realist empiricism: that scientific knowledge can arrive at statements about unobservable structures that are approximately true, and that the basis of evaluation of such hypotheses is through appropriate use of empirical methods (observation, experimentation, and historical inquiry).  Marx’s own writings do not support a relativistic “sociology of knowledge,” according to which the validity of knowledge depends on the social class perspective of the investigator; instead, his theory of knowledge is premised on the notion that well-founded beliefs about the social world can be arrived at on the basis of empirical methods and theoretical reasoning.

      What about metaphysics and ontology?  Here Marx’s work is somewhat more distinctive.  He presupposes a number of metaphysical assumptions about societies and historical processes: that the social world is a causal order, that social structures have properties and causal characteristics, that individuals constitute social structures through their actions and choices, that “social formations” fall under the categories of “modes of production,” that modes of production consist of sets of forces and relations of production, and that classes exist.  Each of these assumptions serves as a part of Marx’s social ontology.  They represent assumptions about the kinds of entities and relations that exist in the world that are, in a sense, prior to specific empirical discoveries.  (This does not imply that they are beyond the reach of empirical inquiry, however; the test of the ontology is the empirical success or failure of the more specific theories that are launched within its terms.)

      Marx’s ontology includes several more specific ideas as well.  The ideas of the forces and relations of production are critical to his inquiry; these ideas capture the level of technology and the institutional context in which the technology is utilized that are current within a given society.  (This pair of ideas can be summarized as “technology and power.”)  The concept of exploitation is also crucial in Marx’s ontology; it describes a relation within the context of which some individuals and groups are enabled to control the labor time of others and to derive benefit from their labor without compensation.  The labor theory of value, and the theory of surplus value, provide an analytical framework within which to theorize about exploitation.  Marx’s concepts of alienation, fetishism, and mystification are also foundational in his social ontology.  Individuals have consciousness and freedom, but they find themselves always within the context of institutions and ideas that structure their understandings of the relations that govern them.  (“Men make their own history, but not in circumstances of their own making;” (Marx 1964).)

The twentieth century trail breakers

      Let us turn briefly to a review of some of the directions that Marxian thought has taken in the twentieth century. 

Althusser

      Louis Althusser’s reading of Marx is a particularly philosophical reading (Althusser and Balibar 1970).  Althusser attributes to Marxism a philosophical theory, an epistemology, and a series of theoretical concepts, through which he believes that Marxism seeks to view the world.  (It is perhaps significant that Althusser generally does not attribute this theory to Marx, but to Marxism.  It illustrates Althusser’s preference for the system over the author, the structure over the agent, and the abstract over the concrete.)  The concepts of structural determination, overdetermination, and determination in the last instance are his central contributions, and they provide a singularly philosophical and apriori basis for inquiry into real historical processes.

      Is Marx’s system an effort in empirical discovery?  Althusser’s answer, on the whole, is that it is not.  Instead, it is an effort in conceptualizing history in terms of abstract structures and contradictions; it is an effort in philosophy.  He is highly critical of empiricism as a basis for social knowledge. 

      Althusser’s is a structuralist theory that verges on logical idealism—the notion that reality can be recapitulated entirely through theoretical argument.  Althusser emphasizes the “reading” rather than the real object that is read; that is, he emphasizes a reading of Capital rather than an interrogation of real, historically given capitalism.

      Althusser represents the “anti-humanist” Marx (Althusser 1969 : 221ff.).  He rejects the notion that the theory of human nature and alienation represent core elements of Marxism (the central contributions of the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts and other early writings), and puts it forward that it is the theory of the abstract structure of capitalism advanced in Capital that represents Marx’s core contribution. 

      Much of Althusser’s writing on Marx falls in the category of social metaphysics: articulating a series of concepts designed to express the nature of the structures and relations that constitute a historical whole.  His notion of “a structure in dominance” is designed to capture the notion that the various spheres of social life—economic, legal, political, etc.—are part of a complex whole (Althusser 1969 : 201). 

      Let us ask the critical question from the point of view of this chapter: does Althusser put forward a method for Marxist inquiry?  In the sense that is before us here—a method of inquiry designed to probe contingent historical and empirical processes—he does not.  He rather constructs a philosopher’s method of reading and theorizing, analyzing and extending, the thoughts expressed in a complex text.  In this fashion his work is more akin to literary theory than it is to empirical scientific inquiry.  His goal is to extract the “problematic” of a given complex text (Capital), rather than inquiring into the empirical properties of a real system (capitalism).  (Callinicos 1976)

      Althusser’s theorizing about Marx influenced several other important figures in European Marxism, including particularly Nicos Poulantzas.  Poulantzas undertook extensive analysis of politics within the general framework of Althusser’s formulation of the mode of production (Poulantzas 1973; Poulantzas 1975).  His work, however, is based on historical investigation and research in ways that Althusser’s work never was; as a consequence, it has the potential to make a significant contribution to our understanding of political power within capitalism.  “The object of this book is the political, in particular the political superstructure of the state in the CMP: that is the production of the concept of this region in this mode, and the production of more concrete concepts dealing with politics in capitalist social formations” (Poulantzas 1973 : 16).  Poulantzas attempts to provide an historically informed theory of the state within the framework of an Althusserian formulation of the concept of the capitalist mode of production.

      It is fair to ask of Poulantzas whether the political formations he studies display any form of contingency; or whether, in his view, they unfold as a clockwork in reflex to the functioning of the mode of production as a whole.  Is there anything to be learned from detailed factual study?  Or is it thought that all features of capitalist society are implicitly coded in the logic of the mode of production?  If the answer is “no”, then Poulantzas’ work falls in the category of materialist philosophy; if it is “yes”, then we can have at least some preliminary confidence that Poulantzas is open to pursuing real social science research.  Fortunately for the standing of Poulantzas’ political inquiry, there is evidence in his work that he recognizes the contingency of many features of the capitalist state and capitalist politics.  He emphasizes the “relative autonomy” of the state—reflecting the notion that the political sphere does not simply dance on the strings of the economic structure (Poulantzas 1973 : 255ff.).  He makes a serious effort to discover the characteristics of bureaucracy and “state apparatus”—again, a set of features that do not derive from the abstract logic of the CMP (Poulantzas 1973 : 325ff.).  And, in his treatment of the fascist state, he make a genuine historical effort to discover the particular contingencies through which this state form emerged within those historical and economic circumstances (Poulantzas 1974).[2]

Gramsci

      Gramsci’s work can be summarized in several themes, including one significant methodological innovation.  Writing in the early years of Italian fascism, his central topic is the question, how was it possible for fascist parties to emerge from capitalist society?  International socialists prior to World War I predicted the rise of mass socialist parties of workers; whereas Italy and Germany witnessed the rise of fascism, grounded in other and “non-essential” classes.  How could this have occurred within the assumptions of Marxist political theory?  In what ways are politics, political consciousness, and political movements autonomous relative to the economic formations of society?

      One of Gramsci’s most fundamental contributions is his concept of hegemony (Gramsci 1957).  He accords a significant degree of autonomy to the social processes of consciousness formation.  There are concrete cultural institutions through which individuals’ social consciousness (their “ideology”) is shaped, and these institutions are objects of struggle among powerful agents within society.  According to a mechanistic theory of ideology, the consciousness of the dominant class determines the consciousness of subordinate classes as well.  Gramsci’s innovation is to recognize that there is an active struggle over the terms of social consciousness, and that specific institutions—newspapers, universities, labor unions, chambers of commerce, factories, political rallies—have active influence on the frameworks of thought and interpretation through which various groups view the world.  These institutions are therefore the object of active struggle among contending groups, and the outcome of these struggles is not pre-ordained.  Groups can exercise “hegemony” by establishing the prominence of their guiding assumptions within the core of these institutions of consciousness.

      What is the methodological significance of this insight?  It is to strike an important blow for relaxing a common Marxist assumption of a relation of determination between the economic structure and the elements of the “superstructure.”  Gramsci is one of the prominent voices of the twentieth century who sought to reduce the economic determinism of the theory and to leave room for relative autonomy in the spheres of the political, cultural, and mobilizational.  His approach gives expression to the role of agency within class politics, and therefore to some extent reduces the primacy of the structural (the economic structure, the mode of production).

      It is also pertinent to ask, what is the epistemic basis of Gramsci’s theories?  He was not a scholarly researcher; instead, he was a thoughtful observer-participant-theoretician.  The most compelling aspects of his theories derive from his reflections on the political processes in Italy between the wars in which he was directly involved—the working-class politics of Turin, the socialist and communist movements of inter-war Italy, and his observations of the rise of the fascist movement in Italy.[3]  His laboratory was inter-war Italy, and his instruments were his own participation and his powers of observation and diagnosis.

Critical theory

      Among the most important theorists of Marxism in the twentieth century fell in the category of the school of “critical theory”, including Adorno, Horkheimer, and Marcuse. This school of thought emphasized the concepts of alienation, fetishism, and critique, and cast strong doubt on the “scientism” of vulgar Marxism.  This group of thinkers has not made a substantial contribution to positive thinking about social science methodology, however; their contributions have tended to move Marxism in the direction of philosophy and literature rather than empirical and historical research.  A partial exception to this statement is Jurgen Habermas.  Habermas succeeds in bringing together a deep philosophical perspective on problems of politics, rationality, and history with a respect for empirical and theoretical approach to social science research.  However, his work too falls at a level of generality that permits it to have little real influence on social science inquiry.

Materialist history

      E. P. Thompson is one of the great historians of the twentieth century.  And he has made a profound contribution to Marxist historiography.  His most important book, The Making of the English Working Class (Thompson 1966), provides what is perhaps the single most sustained, historically grounded, and illuminating accounts of class formation to be found in the literature.  His own relationship to a Marxist political movement was complex (Thompson 1995), and his break with Stalinist politics was unambiguous.  The genius of his historical writing, and his outstanding contribution to Marxist method in the twentieth century, is his open interrogation of the historical steps through which a particular class formation, the English working class, came to be.  There is no dogmatism in his account, and no simple “orrery” of theory (Thompson 1995).  Instead, there is a highly rigorous and detailed study of the elements of class formation in the circumstances of English history.  He provides great insight and detail into the organizations, churches, and associations through which the English working class came to constitute itself as such.  And Thompson makes it clear that there is nothing mechanical about the formation of class consciousness—no automatic transition from “class in itself” to “class for itself.”  Instead, the formation of class consciousness is the result of particular institutions and choices at particular junctures in history.  Thus Thompson emphasizes the “subjective” and historically specific evolution of class consciousness.  And this approach implies that different circumstances can give rise to different configurations of class. 

      Other Marxist historians of the twentieth century have shown similar historiographic rigor.  Perry Anderson, Albert Soboul, and Marc Bloch, each in his own way, has begun with a broad Marxist perspective, and has then conducted historical research with an open mind and without ideological fixed points.  Bloch, for example, begins with a generally materialist view of the influence of technology and property on other dimensions of social development.  But he then inquires with historical precision into such topics as the diffusion of the wheeled plow, the property relations that facilitated the adoption of this technology, and the village-level politics that were most well-adapted to these property relations (Bloch 1966).  Soboul begins with the general perspective that class conflict is the key to understanding the French Revolution; he then undertakes the detailed historical research that is needed to track the movements and impulses that led to the stages of the French Revolution.  Perry Anderson focuses on the property system and political structure of the “second feudalism” and attempts to explain the course that Eastern Europe took (Anderson 1974).

      In each instance the historian takes his craft with great seriousness.  The tools of historical research, and the values of truthful inquiry, drive the historical project; and the authors are prepared to discover connections, contingencies, and anomalies (relative to the theory of historical materialism).  Specifically, each author leaves dogma at the door, and expends great effort and openness of mind to discern the institutions and processes that transpire within the historical domain under investigation.[4]  At the same time, however, these historians have been guided by the style of inquiry formulated by Marx and extended by others.

Analytical Marxism

      The 1980s saw a lively expansion of interest in Marxist theory among analytic philosophers and social scientists.  These debates led to a fairly convincing set of answers to questions about a number of important topics: Marx’s critique of justice, his theory of exploitation, his ideas about social science method, his economic theories, and his theory of historical materialism.  The topics that structured debates throughout the decade largely focused on Marx's theory of history and his economic philosophy.  And significantly, these debates drew largely on Marx's later writings, extending from the German Ideology, through the Grundrisse and Capital.  Marx is regarded as a social scientist, with a scientific treatment of capitalism as the basis of his critique of modern society and an organized theory of history as context for his theory of historical change and revolution.  And much of the work that has emerged from these debates has been as much oriented toward construction of a more adequate social science as it has to formulating a social philosophy.  In other words: analytical Marxism has made more of a contribution to the foundations of the social sciences than to social philosophy.

      The general approach has been an effort to bring the tools of rational choice theory, neo-classical economics, and contemporary political science models to bear on classic Marxian problems: exploitation, domination, historical change, the workings of a social property system, and the ways in which interests inflect political choices.

Marx’s influence on 20th century social science

      Let us return now to the “style of research” that is embodied in Marxian social science.  These points will serve to capture Marx’s main contributions to social science inquiry (from at least my perspective).  Marx’s writings constitute a “style of research” for subsequent researchers that consists of a related family of assumptions and perspectives.  Let us now attempt to identify some of the most important contributions of Marx’s work for the social sciences in the twentieth century.  Seen in broad strokes, important themes would include:

 

·      Emphasis on the significance of class—for people and for social change

·      Focus on institutions of production, technology, property (modes of production, forces and relations of production)

·      Concept of alienation

·      Theory of value and surplus value

·      Formulation of an economic theory of capitalism

·      Theory of exploitation

·      Framework for understanding the pre-capitalist history of Europe and sketches of Asia

·      Sketches of alternatives to capitalism—socialist institutions

 

      These points can be transformed into a series of substantive methodological maxims for social research; as such, they have wielded enormous influence on social scientific and historical research throughout the twentieth century:

 

·      Seek out the “material” institutions—property, technology, labor

·      Examine non-material institutions from the point of view of their role within a social system of production and control.  Ideology, state, culture.

·      Examine the nature of inter-group exploitation; the schemes of domination that these require; and the forms of struggle that result

·      Pay attention to the lived experience of persons within social institutions

·      Examine the centrality of class structures—lived experience, exploitation, behavior and incentive, social change

·      Identify enduring structures—economic, political, cultural—through which the activities of individuals within society are channeled

 

      On this approach, Marx does not offer a distinctive method of social science inquiry; rather, he provides an eclectic and empirically informed effort to describe and explain the phenomena of capitalism.  Marx provides a “style of inquiry” based on a family of hypotheses, hunches, and ontological commitments.  Through this inquiry he provides a substantive contribution to social science, in the form of a series of descriptive and theoretical insights; particularly about the institutional anatomy and dynamics of capitalism and social behavior.  Dialectical thinking is not a part of Marx’s method of social inquiry; at most, a source of hypotheses about “finding contradictions”.  Finally, the tools of rational choice theory and neo-classical economics are highly consonant with Marxist thinking.

      On this approach, Marx’s body of research does not represent a catechism; it does not constitute an “organon” in its leather case.  It is more akin to a research programme in Lakatos’s sense: a body of large hypotheses, suggestions for fertile areas to examine, paradigm explanations, theories, and interpretation; some bits of formal theory (e.g., the labor theory of value).  To work within the programme is to acquire the “tacit knowledge” that emerges from careful study of the many examples of fertile inquiry (Thompson, Bloch, Morishima) and then pursuing social inquiry on one’s own domain in a way that is creatively informed by the body of work—but also by the best non-marxist work—for example, Sabel, Work and Politics (Sabel 1982).

      “Method” implies a prescriptive body of doctrines to guide inquiry.  Certainly Marx does not offer such a body of doctrines.  If anything, he would subscribe to a fairly ordinary prescription—familiar from Mill (Mill 1950) or Whewell (Whewell and Butts 1968)— along these lines:

 

·      formulate theories and hypotheses

·      engage in careful study of existing empirical and historical data

·      discern “patterns” in data that suggest hypotheses

·      evaluate hypotheses through empirical and factual inquiry

 

The more directive parts of Marx’s methodology—but now loose and heuristic—look more like this—

 

·      Examine material institutions

·      Look at class, power, exploitation, domination

·      Don’t be blinded to effects that violate the materialist dicta

·      Be mindful of “contradictions” that work themselves through historical contingencies

·      Look for underlying causes and structures

 

      How, then, should we think about the professional preparation of the young social scientist and historian?  Is it similar to that of the young biologist or physicist?  No, it is not.  The social sciences differ from natural science in being inherently more amorphous and eclectic, and this derives from the nature of social phenomena (Little 1998).  There are highly specific research strategies, lab procedures, and foundational theories in the natural sciences.  So the young molecular biologist must master a very specific paradigm of precise theories, mechanisms, and structures; as well as authoritative strategies of experimentation and inquiry. But the case is quite different in the social sciences.  There we will find no general theory of society, or privileged mode of inquiry for social research.  So the best advise for young researchers in the social sciences is to be eclectic and open-minded: learn a variety of tools, explanatory strategies, and foundational hypotheses and powerful examples of social inquiry.  And pursue a strong understanding of some of the most imaginative social scientists and researchers of the past generation, whatever their paradigm (e.g. Hirschman or Skinner; Sabel, Tilly, or Scott).  Then address the phenomena of interest with an open mind.

Conclusion

      Here we have surveyed some of Marx’s central contributions to social science research, and some of the most important ideas that twentieth century thinkers have brought to bear on Marxist social inquiry.  Is there such a thing as “Marxist social science”?  No, if the point of reference is molecular biology as a paradigm of research.  But yes, if we are thinking instead of a loose research programme, inspired by a congeries of hypotheses, insights, and salient powerful interpretations, which the researcher can then have in mind as she sorts through her own research problems.

      The root cause of this eclectic nature of the best social research lies in the nature of social phenomena themselves.  The social world is not well ordered.  It is not a law-governed system of cause and effect.  Instead, it is a sum of many different and cross-cutting processes, structures and institutions, mediated by the purposive meaningful actions of persons, within given cultural and material institutions that bear contingent and sometimes accidental relations to each other.

      And Marxist thinking, appropriately eclectically construed, has much to offer as we try to make sense of that plural world.


References

Akerlof, George. 1970. The Market for 'Lemons': Quality, Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism. Quarterly Journal of Economics 84:488-500.

Althusser, Louis. 1969. For Marx. [1st American ] ed. New York,: Pantheon Books.

Althusser, Louis, and Etienne Balibar. 1970. Reading Capital. London: New Left Books.

Anderson, Perry. 1974. Lineages of the absolutist state. London: New Left Books.

Arrow, Kenneth Joseph. 1963. Social choice and individual values. 2d ed, Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University. Monograph 12. New York,: Wiley.

Aston, T. H., and C. H. E. Philpin. 1985. The Brenner debate : agrarian class structure and economic development in pre-industrial Europe, Past and present publications. Cambridge [Cambridgeshire] ; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Bloch, Marc Léopold Benjamin. 1966. French rural history; an essay on its basic characteristics. Berkeley,: University of California Press.

Boggs, Carl. 1976. Gramsci's Marxism. London: Pluto Press.

Bowles, Samuel, and Herbert Gintis. 1976. Schooling in capitalist America : educational reform and the contradictions of economic life. New York: Basic Books.

Brenner, Robert. 1976. Agrarian Class Structure and Economic Development in Pre-Industrial Europe. Past and Present 70:30-75.

———. 1982. The Agrarian Roots of European Capitalism. Past and Present 97:16-113.

Brinton, Mary C., and Victor Nee. 1998. New institutionalism in sociology. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

Callinicos, Nicos. 1976. Althusser's marxism. London: Pluto Press.

Carr, Edward Hallett. 1984. The Comintern and the Spanish Civil War. 1st American ed. New York: Pantheon Books.

Dobb, Maurice. 1963. Studies in the Development of Capitalism. New York: International Publishers.

Elster, Jon. 1982. Marxism, Functionalism, and Game Theory. Theory and Society 11:453-482.

———. 1985. Making Sense of Marx. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

———. 1986. Three challenges to class. In Analytical Marxism, edited by J. Roemer.

Engels, Friedrich. 1958. The condition of the working class in England. Oxford: B. Blackwell.

Finley, M. I. 1973. The Ancient Economy. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Giddens, Anthony. 1973. The class structure of the advanced societies, Hutchinson university library: sociology. London,: Hutchinson.

Gramsci, Antonio. 1957. The modern prince, and other writings. London: Lawrence and Wishart.

Hindess, Barry, and Paul Q. Hirst. 1975. Pre-capitalist Modes of Production. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Jones, Gareth Stedman. 1971. Outcast London: a study in the relationship between classes in Victorian society. Oxford [Eng.]: Clarendon Press.

Knight, Jack. 1992. Institutions and social conflict, The Political economy of institutions and decisions. Cambridge [England] ; New York, N.Y.: Cambridge University Press.

Kuhn, Thomas S. 1970. The structure of scientific revolutions. [2d , enl. ed, International encyclopedia of unified science. Foundations of the unity of science, v. 2, no. 2. Chicago,: University of Chicago Press.

Lakatos, Imre. 1970. Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes . In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge , edited by I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave.

Lakatos, Imre, and Alan Musgrave. 1974. Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Repr. with corrections 1974. ed, Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science, London, 1965 ; v. 4. Cambridge [Eng.] ; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Little, Daniel. 1986. The Scientific Marx. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

———. 1987. Dialectics and Science in Marx's Capital. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 17:197-220.

———. 1993. On the Scope and Limits of Generalizations in the Social Sciences. Synthese.

———. 1998. Microfoundations, Method and Causation: On the Philosophy of the Social Sciences. New Brunswick, New Jersey: Transaction Publishers.

Mandel, Ernest. 1969. Marxist economic theory. [Rev. ] ed. New York,: M[onthly] R[eview] Press.

———. 1975. Late capitalism. Revised ed. London; Atlantic Highlands [N.J.]: New Left Books ; Humanities Press.

Marx, Karl. 1964. The eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte. With explanatory notes. New York,: International Publishers.

———. 1977. Capital. Vol. 1. New York: Vintage.

Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. 1975. Karl Marx and Frederick Engels; selected correspondence. 3rd revised ed. Moscow,: Foreign Languages Pub. House.

Mészáros, István. 1972. Marx's theory of alienation, Harper torchbooks. New York,: Harper & Row.

Miliband, Ralph. 1969. The State in Capitalist Society . New York : Basic.

———. 1982. Capitalist Democracy in Britain . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Mill, John Stuart. 1950. Philosophy of Scientific Method. New York : Hafner.

Ollman, Bertell. 1971. Alienation: Marx's conception of man in capitalist society, Cambridge studies in the history and theory of politics. Cambridge [Eng.]: University Press.

———. 1993. Dialectical investigations. New York: Routledge.

Olson, Mancur. 1965. The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Poulantzas, Nicos. 1973. Political Power and Social Class. London: New Left Books.

Poulantzas, Nicos Ar. 1974. Fascism and dictatorship : the Third International and the problem of fascism. London: Nlb.

———. 1975. Classes in contemporary capitalism. London: Nlb.

Powell, Walter W., and Paul J. DiMaggio. 1996. The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis. Theory, culture & society 60 (4):529(10).

Przeworski, Adam. 1985. Capitalism and Social Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

———. 1985. Marxism and Rational Choice . Politics & Society 14 (4):379-409.

———. 1986. Material interests, class compromise, and socialism. In Analytical Marxism, edited by J. Roemer.

Ringer, Fritz. 1997. Max Weber's Methodology: The Unification of the Cultural and Social Sciences. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Roemer, John. 1981. Analytical Foundations of Marxism . New York : Cambridge University Press.

———. 1982. A General Theory of Exploitation and Class . Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

———. 1982. Methodological Individualism and Deductive Marxism. Theory and Society  11:513-520.

———. 1986. 'Rational Choice' Marxism: Some Issues of Method and Substance. In Analytical Marxism, edited by J. Roemer.

———, ed. 1986. Analytical Marxism . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Ruben, D.-H. 1979. Marxism and Dialectics. In Issues in Marxist Philosophy vol. 1, edited by J. Mepham and D.-H. Ruben.

Sabel, Charles F. 1982. Work and politics : the division of labor in industry, Cambridge studies in modern political economies. Cambridge [Cambridgeshire] ; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Schaff, Adam. 1970. Marxism and the human individual. New York,: McGraw-Hill.

Sennett, Richard, and Jonathan Cobb. 1972. The hidden injuries of class. [1st ] ed. New York,: Knopf.

Soboul, Albert. 1989. The French Revolution, 1787-1799 : from the storming of the Bastille to Napoleon. London ; Boston: Unwin Hyman.

Szymanski, Albert. 1978. The Capitalist State and the Politics of Class. Cambridge, MA: Winthrop.

Thompson, E. P. 1966. The making of the English working class, Vintage books, V-322. New York,: Vintage Books.

———. 1995. The poverty of theory, or An orrery of errors. New ed. London: Merlin Press.

Whewell, William, and Robert E. Butts. 1968. William Whewell's theory of scientific method. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

 



[1] Many of these questions are explored in detail in The Scientific Marx (Little 1986).

[2] For powerful and effective criticisms of another Althusserian effort at social theory, see E. P. Thompson’s critique of Hindess and Hirst (Hindess and Hirst 1975) in The Poverty of Theory (Thompson 1995).

[3] See Carl Boggs’ treatment of the development of Gramsci’s thought (Boggs 1976).

[4] Other good examples of materialist history include Carr (Carr 1984), Finley (Finley 1973), Dobb (Dobb 1963), and Brenner (Brenner 1976, 1982), (Aston and Philpin 1985).

Return to Home Page