Return to research page

Plasticity of the Social

Daniel Little

University of Michigan-Dearborn

 

Social Science History Association

November, 2007

Abstract

The paper takes up the issue of "reification" in sociological thinking: the tendency to imagine that social entities have fixed, semi-permanent characteristics, and that they fall into "social kinds" that recur across historical settings. Examples of concepts that are often reified include revolutions, states, riots, labor unions, and classes. Against the presupposition that social things like these have fixed and recurring properties, the paper argues for the contingency, path-dependence, and plasticity of social things.

 

The topic of this panel—“Persistence and Change in Large Social Patterns”— might appear to suggest a huge inconsistency in the way we frame our thinking about the social world.  It brings to mind two fundamentally opposed strands of ancient Greek philosophy about the natural world—Plato’s universal and unchanging universe and Heraclitus’s view of the universe as flux.  But actually the point of the panel is more mundane than this.  It is intended to bring us to recognize two points about the social world that are simultaneously true: first, that social institutions and practices are inherently plastic in their constitution; and second, that there are nonetheless recognizable social mechanisms that secure a sometimes remarkable degree of persistence in the features of a given social arrangement or outcome.  My paper emphasizes the reasons why we should expect that social arrangements are plastic, but I will also address some of the mechanisms that permit persistence in the face of deliberate, unintended, or entropic pressures for change.  Other papers will emphasize the dimension of persistence in large social patterns.

The topic makes a difference for social scientists, because the “ontological” assumptions we bring to a domain of investigation have a large effect on shaping the theories, methods, and analyses that we arrive at.  If we expect to find “atoms” or “vortices” in our study of nature, then our theories are likely to reflect these ontologies; likewise, if we imagine that the social world consists of essential social structures, then we are likely to attempt to organize our observations and theories around such structures. So it is important to have as well-grounded an ontology of the social as we can.[1]

A fundamental social ontology: methodological localism

My approach today is grounded in a theory of social ontology that I refer to as methodological localism (ML) (Little 2006).  This theory of social entities affirms that there are large social structures and facts that influence social outcomes.  But it insists that these structures are only possible insofar as they are embodied in the actions and states of socially constructed individuals.  The “molecule” of all social life is the socially constructed and socially situated individual, who lives, acts, and develops within a set of local social relationships, institutions, norms, and rules.  With methodological individualism, this position embraces the point that individuals are the bearers of social structures and causes.  There is no such thing as an autonomous social force; rather, all social properties and effects are conveyed through the individuals who constitute a population at a time.  Against individualism, however, methodological localism affirms the “social-ness” of social actors.  Methodological localism denies the possibility or desirability of characterizing the individual extra-socially.  Instead, the individual is understood as a socially constituted actor, affected by large current social facts such as value systems, social structures, extended social networks, and the like.  In other words, ML denies the possibility of reductionism from the level of the social to the level of a population of non-social individuals.  Rather, the individual is formed by locally embodied social facts, and the social facts are in turn constituted by the current characteristics of the persons who make them up. 

This account begins with the socially constituted person. Human beings are subjective, intentional, and relational agents. They interact with other persons in ways that involve competition and cooperation. They form relationships, enmities, alliances, and networks; they compose institutions and organizations. They create material embodiments that reflect and affect human intentionality. They acquire beliefs, norms, practices, and worldviews, and they socialize their children, their friends, and others with whom they interact. Some of the products of human social interaction are short-lived and local (indigenous fishing practices); others are long-duration but local (oral traditions, stories, and jokes); and yet others are built up into social organizations of great geographical scope and extended duration (states, trade routes, knowledge systems). But always we have individual agents interacting with other agents, making use of resources (material and social), and pursuing their goals, desires, and impulses.

            Social action takes place within spaces that are themselves socially structured by the actions and purposes of others—by property, by prejudice, by law and custom, and by systems of knowledge. So our account needs to identify the local social environments through which action is structured and projected: the inter-personal networks, the systems of rules, the social institutions. The social thus has to do with the behaviorally, cognitively, and materially embodied reality of social institutions. An institution, we might say, is an embodied set of rules, incentives, and opportunities that have the potential of influencing agents’ choices and behavior.[2]  An institution is a complex of socially embodied powers, limitations, and opportunities within which individuals pursue their lives and goals. A property system, a legal system, and a professional baseball league all represent examples of institutions.[3]  Institutions have effects that are in varying degrees independent from the individual or “larger” than the individual. Each of these social entities is embodied in the social states of a number of actors—their beliefs, intentions, reasoning, dispositions, and histories. Actors perform their actions within the context of social frameworks represented as rules, institutions, and organizations, and their actions and dispositions embody the causal effectiveness of those frameworks. And institutions influence individuals by offering incentives and constraints on their actions, by framing the knowledge and information on the basis of which they choose, and by conveying sets of normative commitments (ethical, religious, interpersonal) that influence individual action.

It is important to emphasize that ML affirms the existence of social constructs beyond the purview of the individual actor or group.  Political institutions exist—and they are embodied in the actions and states of officials, citizens, criminals, and opportunistic others.  These institutions have real effects on individual behavior and on social processes and outcomes—but always mediated through the structured circumstances of agency of the myriad participants in these institutions and the affected society.  This perspective emphasizes the contingency of social processes, the mutability of social structures over space and time, and the variability of human social systems (norms, urban arrangements, social practices, and so on).

What is plasticity?

First, what do I mean by “plastic”?  I mean that the properties of the social entity or practice can change over time; they are not rigid, fixed, or timeless. They are not bound into consistent and unchanging categories of entities. Molecules of water preserve their physical characteristics no matter what.  In contrast to natural substances such as gold or water, social things can change their properties indefinitely. So the contrary to “plastic” might be “unchanging and fixed by an essential set of properties.”

This interpretation emphasizes “plastic” as the contrary to “static and fixed”. A second way in which an entity might be unchanging is as a dynamic equilibrium.  A social structure might be a self-correcting system that restores its equilibrium characteristics in the face of disturbing influences.  The temperature in this room is subject to external influences that would result in change; but the thermostat provides cool or warm air as needed to bring the office temperature back to the equilibrium value. When I say that social entities are plastic, I also mean to say that they are not generally determined within a dynamic equilibrium (as sociological functionalism maintains, perhaps), with powerful homeostatic mechanisms that correct for disturbing influences. There is no “essential” form to which the structure tends to return in equilibrium.

This ontology emphasizes a deep plasticity and heterogeneity in social entities.  Organizations and institutions change over time and place.  Agents within these organizations change their characteristics through their own behavior, through their intentional efforts to modify them, and through the cumulative effect of agents and behavior over time and place.  Social constructs are caused and implemented within a substrate of purposive and active agents whose behavior and mentality at a given time determine the features of the social entity.  As individuals act, pursue their interests, notice new opportunities, and innovate, they simultaneously “reproduce” a given institution and also erode or change the institution.  So I maintain that institutions are not fully homeostatic, preserving their own structure in the face of disturbances.  This is not to say that institutions lack such homeostatic mechanisms altogether; only that we cannot presuppose that a given institution or organization will persist in its fundamental characteristics over extended time and space.

A brief example will illustrate the kinds of plasticity and variation that I am thinking of.  Take the tenure process in American universities.  We can see an overall similarity in processes, rules, and goals in the tenure processes at various institutions.  Organization is to some extent influenced by function.  But we also see substantial variation and drift in both process and content (criteria and processes for awarding tenure).  For example, there are some universities that are incorporating “community service” into tenure criteria.  Different universities give a different balance of faculty review and provost and dean review.  There are different cultures of seriousness in review by faculty committees and academic administrators.  Different institutions define different institutional goals: enhance national reputation of the faculty (through research productivity), improve teaching, orient faculty to community service, …  There is a visible push-pull by stakeholders on these institutions: deans, provosts, presidents; faculty governance units; individual faculty.  There have been changes in the past 20 years that have affected many institutions: post-tenure review, greater willingness to do reviews leading to removal, …  So tenure institutions display the variability and plasticity that I believe is inherent in all social institutions.

So far I have focused on institutions and organizations.  But features of social consciousness and social identity are also variable across time, place, and group.  The mechanisms through which social identities and mentalities are transmitted, transmuted, and maintained are varied; inculcation, imitation, and common circumstances are central among these.  But the transmission of an identity is a bit like the transmission of a message through a telephone chain.  Because of “noise” in the system, because of individual differences among the transmitters, and because of multiple other influences on micro-identities, we should expect great variation within and across groups with regard to the particulars of their social identities.

The plasticity of identities, norms, and mental frameworks is particularly great.  The mechanisms of transmission invite variation across successive instances and generations.  Local variations will take root in sub-populations.  There are limited mechanisms of homeostasis.  And individuals and groups have the ability to modify the content and meaning of these elements of social consciousness more or less indefinitely over time. Small variations in locally-embodied content proliferate through imitation and parent-child transmission.

The example of early-modern ocean-going boat design serves to illustrate the concept of plasticity with regard to socially embodied practices and knowledge.  If we observe the design features of Scandinavian boats over a four-hundred year stretch of time, we see a shifting of basic design characteristics at every level of description (Elster 1983), (Sverrisson 2002).  Skilled builders and designers notice opportunities for improvement in design in response to a specific feature of the ocean environment or the needs of the warriors or fishermen who use the boats; new materials become available and get incorporated into design; new technologies for steering or sail-management diffuse from other cultures; and the overall result is that the look, feel, and capabilities of the boat change significantly over time.  The ocean environment dictates some design features as obviously best—we never see a boat design with a flat prow, given the need to cut through the water; but most features have alternative embodiments that would do about as well.  The analogy is illuminating for social institutions; the forces of innovation, redesign in response to needs and environmental conditions, diffusion, and the play of individuals in relation to the structure all play important roles in both the evolution of a technology and the transformation of a social institution.

We might also say that individuals too are “plastic”.  The social psychology of the existing person is the product of the individual’s earlier experiences, education, and training.  So this particular person—perhaps now a “rational maximizer with racial prejudice and a fear of flying”—has been constructed through a concrete set of experiences.  But (a) this concrete present individual herself can be brought to change some basic motivational and psychological characteristics through additional experiences—perhaps diversity training and a positive experience with a person of another race; and (b) other individuals from a similar background can be brought to have a different set of motivational characteristics through different circumstances of development.  So the individual’s basic characteristics of personality, belief, and motivation are plastic.

In each case we find that institutions, practices, and social identities show a substantial degree of plasticity over time and place.  And this is what we should expect--fundamentally, because we can sketch out the social processes and mechanisms through which institutions are formed, maintained, and modified. Institutions are human products and are embodied in human actions and beliefs.  Sometimes an institution is designed through a deliberative process; sometimes it results through a series of uncoordinated adaptations and appropriations by a number of participants.  Institutions solve social problems; they coordinate individual activity, control resources, allocate benefits and burdens.  And institutions either maintain their structure or change depending on the interests and actions of the participants.  The participants in institutions interact with the particulars of the organization in ways that improve the effectiveness of the organization, or better serve a particular set of interests, or some combination of both.  Leaders may determine that a modification of the institution would increase the capacity of the organization to deliver services, reduce costs, or improve their own ability to control activities within the organization.  Participants may modify the organization in their own ways—through spontaneous local modifications of process; foot-dragging as a way of impeding the functioning of unpopular aspects of the organization; collaboration with other participants to modify the institution in directions more favorable to their interests; etc.

We can identify specific mechanisms of institutional evolution and diffusion that plainly raises the likelihood of plastic change:

 

·      The spread of institutions through imitation invites innovation in local implementation.

·      Spread of institutions through “absorption” likewise permits innovation and adoption of local variants.

·      Reproduction of the organization through successive leaders and members introduces the likelihood of change and adaptation.

Social mechanisms that preserve institutional form

So if institutions and individuals are inherently plastic, then it is a serious problem for research to identify the mechanisms through which persistence is achieved.  As we know from a variety of sources, including Kathleen’s study of skilled-labor regimes, there is significant persistence in a variety of social institutions (Thelen 2004).  There are social mechanisms that produce quasi-stability in institutions and practices, and it is worth identifying and studying these.  For example:

 

 

There are also some perfectly ordinary mechanisms through which we may find similarity in organizational form across distinct institutional embodiments.  For example, it may be that there are important similarities across the news rooms of American and European newspapers.  What might explain these similarities? There are several possible mechanisms.

 

 

This is part of the conceptual basis of comparative sociology; it is worthwhile looking at the details of particular institutions in different settings (for example, Kathleen’s study of skilled labor training institutions; (Thelen 2004)) and asking the related questions of how the instances are different or similar, and what the historical causes are that account for these differences and similarities.

An example: the hospital

Let us think more about the extent and pace of plasticity in social organizations and institutions by considering an example: hospitals. Hospitals are complex social organizations geared towards providing health care for moderately to very needy patients. And the internal organization of hospitals provides a fertile locus for examining issues of institutional change.

            The complexity of a hospital derives from numerous factors: the specialization of medical knowledge (resulting in numerous departments), the multiplicity of business functions (billing, marketing, finance and budget, supervision of doctors, nurses, pharmacists, support staff), the logistical demands of patient care (food, medications, room and bed cleaning), social work needs of patients and families, the regulatory environment, governance institutions, and communication to the public, simply to name the most obvious functions. So a hospital requires the coordinated efforts of hundreds of experts and perhaps thousands of skilled and semi-skilled workers, embodying tens or hundreds of functions. (A mid-sized regional hospital employs several thousand people.)

            Diversity and plasticity comes into this story in several ways. At the mid-level of analysis there are alternative ways of organizing the various functions of the hospital--different ways of organizing human resources, billing, or patient services. That is, structure is underdetermined by functional needs. There are organizational alternatives, and we can expect that there will be actual variation in hospital organization and implementation across the US health system. This variation can be observed at a range of scales: within a region (Atlanta), across regions (Atlanta versus Detroit), or throughout the national system (midwest versus Pacific coast). At the most macro-level, we may observe differences in organization across national systems--US versus Germany or China. (Frank Dobbin's Forging Industrial Policy explores this sort of national-level comparison in application to technology policy frameworks in three countries (Dobbin 1994).)

            But diversity may also be observed over time at the level of the individual hospital. This is sometimes described as "organizational learning"--internal reorganization and redesign so as to better serve patient and business needs in a changing environment. Plasticity comes in here: the organization "mutates" in response to changing needs and new environmental challenges. (Consider some of the ways that hospitals will change as a result of new public reporting requirements concerning cost and morbidity.)

            This mutation may be the result of deliberate choice on the part of hospital administrators (redesign of process). But it may also be the result of broader societal changes leading to changing behavior within the hospital, eventually leading to a change in the routine practices and organizations of the hospital. For example, the operating room of the US hospital of the 1990s is a social space governed explicitly and implicitly by the surgeon (usually male). But imagine the result of a broad values shift towards greater gender equality and less respect for hierarchical authority. We might expect a gradual shift in the operating room towards a team-based approach to surgery. That approach might be confirmed by a record of greater safety (as safety experts in fact expect). And the change might become entrenched in new formal operating rules and procedures--thus changing the institution for a while.

            These arguments show the impulse towards differentiation across hospital structures. There is also an important "centripetal" force that works towards convergence to some degree. This is the process of imitation and the search for "best practices". Consultants are summoned; " how are other hospitals handling this problem of IV infections?" And successful efforts are imitated.

            This example suggests a process of mutation, differentiation, imitation, and occasional convergence. Overall, it supports the vision of institutions as plastic and malleable and responsive to changing individual and societal needs.

Why it matters

            I believe that the social sciences need to be framed out of consideration of a better understanding of the nature of the social—a better social ontology.  The social world is not a system of law-governed processes; it is instead a mix of different sorts of institutions, forms of human behavior, natural and environmental constraints, and contingent events.  The entities that make up the social world at a given time and place have no particular ontological stability; they do not fall into “natural kinds”; and there is no reason to expect deep similarity across a number of ostensibly similar institutions – states, for example, or labor unions.  So the rule for the social world is—heterogeneity, contingency, and plasticity.  And the metaphysics associated with our thinking about the natural world—laws of nature; common, unchanging structures; and predictable processes of change—do not provide appropriate metaphors for our understandings and expectations of the social world; nor do they suggest the right kinds of social science theories and constructs.

            Instead of naturalism, I advocate for an approach to social science theorizing that could be described as post-positivist.  It recognizes that there is a degree of pattern in social life—but emphasizes that these patterns fall far short of the regularities associated with laws of nature.  It emphasizes contingency of social processes and outcomes.   It insists upon the importance and legitimacy of eclectic use of social theory: the processes are heterogeneous, and therefore it is appropriate to appeal to different types of social theories as we explain social processes.  It emphasizes the importance of path-dependence in social outcomes.  It suggests that the most valid scientific statements in the social sciences have to do with the discovery of concrete social-causal mechanisms, through which some types of social outcomes come about.  And finally, it highlights what I call “methodological localism”: the insight that the foundation of social action and outcome is the local, socially-located and socially constructed individual person.  The individual is socially constructed, in that her modes of behavior, thought, and reasoning are created through a specific set of prior social interactions.  And her actions are socially situated, in the sense that they are responsive to the institutional setting in which she chooses to act.  Purposive individuals, embodied with powers and constraints, pursue their goals in specific institutional settings; and regularities of social outcome often result.

            My most central conclusion, however, is ontological.  We ought not think of the social world as a system of phenomena in which we can expect to find a strong underlying order.  Instead, social phenomena are highly diverse, subject to many different and cross-cutting forms of causation.  So the result is that the very strongest regularities that will be ever be discerned will remain the exception-laden phenomenal regularities described here and the highly qualified predictions of regularities that derive from structure-agent analyses.  There is no more fundamental description of the social world in which strong governing regularities drive events and processes.


References

Abbott, Andrew Delano. 1999. Department & discipline : Chicago sociology at one hundred. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Brinton, Mary C., and Victor Nee, eds. 1998. New institutionalism in sociology. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

Dobbin, Frank. 1994. Forging industrial policy : the United States, Britain, and France in the railway age. Cambridge [England] ; New york, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.

Elster, Jon. 1983. Explaining technical change : a case study in the philosophy of science, Studies in rationality and social change. Cambridge [Cambridgeshire] ; New York; Oslo: Cambridge University Press ; Universitetsforlaget.

Ensminger, Jean. 1992. Making a market : the institutional transformation of an African society, The Political economy of institutions and decisions. Cambridge [England] ; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Knight, Jack. 1992. Institutions and social conflict, The Political economy of institutions and decisions. Cambridge [England] ; New York, N.Y.: Cambridge University Press.

Little, Daniel. 2006. Levels the Social. In Handbook for Philosophy of Anthropology and Sociology, edited by S. Turner and M. Risjord. Amsterdam; New York: Elsevier Publishing.

North, Douglass C. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

———. 1998. Economic performance through time. In The New Institutionalism in Sociology, edited by M. C. Brinton and V. Nee.

Sverrisson, Árni. 2002. Small Boats and Large Ships: Social Continuity and Technical Change in the Icelandic Fisheries, 1800-1960. Technology and Culture 43 (2):227-254-3.

Thelen, Kathleen Ann. 2004. How institutions evolve : the political economy of skills in Germany, Britain, the United States, and Japan, Cambridge studies in comparative politics. Cambridge ; New York: Cambridge University Press.

 

 



[1] Andrew Abbott draws attention to the fluidity and permutability of social “entities” (Abbott 1999) : 223).  A social entity is not a fixed thing with stable properties.  It is rather a continuing swirl of linked social activities and practices, themselves linked to other “separate” social traditions.  And particularly important, Abbott endorses a social localism—that all social facts are carried by socially constructed individuals in action.

[2] “Institutions are the humanly devised constraints that structure human interaction. They are made up of formal constraints (for example, rules, laws, constitutions), informal constraints (for example, norms of behavior, conventions, self-imposed codes of conduct), and their enforcement characteristics. Together they define the incentive structure of societies and, specifically, economies” ((North 1998) : 247)).

[3] See (Brinton and Nee 1998), (North 1990), (Ensminger 1992), and (Knight 1992) for recent expositions of the new institutionalism in the social sciences.

Return to research page